Jennifer Swize
Excerpted from: Jennifer Swize , Transracial Adoption and the
Unblinkable Difference: Racial Dissimilarity Serving the Interests of
Adopted Children, Virginia Law Review 1079 - 1118, (September, 2002)(127
Footnotes)(Student Note)
I am ever conscious of the miracle that these children who possess me
to the core of my being are mine and also not mine.
Elizabeth Bartholet, white adoptive parent of two dark-skinned
children
Introduction
TWO-YEAR-OLD Brianna Blackmond was shuffled back and forth between
foster care and her neglectful biological mother. On December 22, 1999,
the judge handling Brianna's custody case ordered the District of
Columbia Child and Family Services to return her to her mother's home.
There Brianna lived with her mother, her godmother, and twelve other
children in a rat-infested, feces- stained home where the children went
without food for days at a time. Two weeks later, Brianna died. Her
godmother had beaten her with a belt and struck fatal blows to her head.
Disapproval of the transracial nature of Brianna's foster home seems
to have contributed to the judge's decision to return Brianna to her
biological mother and, ultimately, to her fate: Brianna was black; her
foster parents were not. Although, typical of family court proceedings,
the judge did not provide a written opinion, she had openly expressed
concerns about transracial placements in response to a similar situation
involving another black child. She stated on the record that the
"'destruction of the black family [through transracial
adoption]"' was driving her "'crazy."'
The horror of Brianna's fate made the front-page news. The stories of
thousands of other black children in the foster care system, however, do
not. Yet, like Brianna's, theirs are also stories about opposition--by
judges, legislators, adoption professionals, and other interested
parties--to placing children with parents of a different race. Driven by
a commitment to biological matching, these decisionmakers seek to place
black children with black parents. The relative lack of black couples
available to adopt, though, makes such matches uncommon. As a result,
black children available for adoption often wait years for permanent
homes, and many are not adopted at all. Instead, they grow up in foster
care, institutional facilities, or, like Brianna, are bounced back and
forth between foster care and biological parents who are incapable of
adequately caring for them. The purpose of this Note is to demonstrate
that such devastating conditions are not justified in light of the
alternative: transracial adoption, or, more specifically, white parents
adopting a black child.
Since transracial adoption surfaced in the 1950s, adoption
professionals, legislators, scholars, and other interested
decisionmakers have debated its capacity to serve the best interests of
adopted children, the legal standard governing adoption petitions. This
ongoing debate has analyzed the effects of transracial adoption and its
ability to foster the benefits presumptively associated with biological
matching, that is, matching a child with adoptive parents in imitation
of biologically-formed families. Opponents of transracial adoption, on
the one hand, argue that children are harmed by transracial placements
because such placements lose the supposed benefits of biological
matching by deviating from that model, because the children's racial
identity suffers, and because black culture is diminished when black
children are raised outside of their racial group. Opponents support a
same-race preference in adoption: children adopted within their racial
group. Advocates of transracial adoption, on the other hand, suggest
that children adopted transracially are not harmed by the diverse family
composition and, moreover, that concerns for the preservation of black
culture are irrelevant in adoption decisions because the best interests
test focuses on the individual child and not on society at large.
Advocates also support transracial adoption as an alternative to the
practical effect of a same-race preference: the significant delay for
thousands of black children awaiting adoption when an otherwise
satisfactory white couple is turned down.
This delay into an adoptive home highlights what is at stake in the
controversy over transracial adoption: the well-being of black children.
Experts agree that delayed placement into a permanent home causes
serious and real harm to a child. To truly flourish, children need the
permanency of a family, and a child's welfare is positively affected the
earlier she becomes part of such a permanent and stable environment.
Research shows that adoptive families provide children a healthier
environment than foster families or institutional facilities.
Under same-race placement regimes, many black children are not placed
in permanent family settings. Instead, they are relegated to a life in
foster care, institutional care, or in the care of neglectful or abusive
parents. They are denied the benefits of a permanent and healthy home,
either for a significant period of time or, often, forever.
Behind the unavailability of homes for black children in a same-race
regime is the mismatch in the number of black children awaiting adoption
and the number of black parents interested in adopting. There is a
relative scarcity of black couples pursuing adoption; at the same time,
there is a disproportionately high number of black children waiting to
be adopted. Thus, a same-race preference results not only in delays for
black children, but also in denials. Because there are not as many black
parents pursuing adoption as there are black children waiting to be
adopted, applying a same-race preference--postponing a black child's
adoption until a racial match is found--often results in no adoption at
all.
Transracial adoption does the opposite: It places a black child in a
permanent family home, and it does so sooner than if the child were
required to wait for a racial match. Where a same-race regime often
denies a loving and permanent family to a black child, transracial
adoption provides one. As Professor Twila Perry, an active participant
in the transracial adoption debate, has stated:
It is indeed a strange "best interests" rule that would
prefer a child to remain in an institution rather than be adopted by a
family already determined by the same agency to be qualified to adopt.
To deny a child a home, even partially on the basis of speculation about
potential racial difficulties sometime in the future, virtually ignores
the value to a child of growing up in a family setting.
Noticeably absent in the debate over application of the best
interests test in adoption is an exposition of the unique benefits that
pertain simply to the observable racial dissimilarity between a black
adopted child and her white adoptive parents. Coined the "unblinkable
difference" by Professor Elizabeth Bartholet, a noted legal scholar
and leading advocate of transracial adoption, the term refers to the
obvious racial dissimilarity between the parents and the child in a
transracial adoption. The term captures a unique element of transracial
adoption and lends itself to further consideration of benefits based on
that element. It may be that the obvious racial difference contributes
to what is in the best interests of the child. If that is the case, then
courts and legislators enforcing a same-race preference improperly
prevent or delay matches.
The role of legislators and courts in applying and interpreting the
best interests standard reinforces the legal nature of the transracial
adoption debate. Although social science scholarship has played a
significant role in the debate, it is the determination of a court,
based on state statutory law, that decides the fate of a child waiting
to be adopted. Congress has also weighed in on the debate, passing
legislation in 1994 and 1996 that, despite its intent to the contrary,
effectively allows race to be considered in adoption decisions. FN24]
Adoption laws thus have a significant and direct impact on the children
involved. Even if a jurisdiction does not expressly favor same-race
adoption over transracial adoption, various actors involved in adoption
placements may perceive transracial adoption in a way that affects its
acceptance and use. If such actors--particularly judges, adoption
professionals, and children's advocates--are swayed by arguments
favoring same-race placement, they are likely to make decisions, at
least some of the time, that delay or foreclose adoption of black
children. If they are persuaded by arguments supporting transracial
adoption, they are likely to reduce or eliminate the delay and place
black children awaiting adoption with permanent families. Thus, the
arguments in this Note will suggest ways for judges, lawyers, adoption
professionals, and other involved parties to support transracial
adoption and question the same-race preference. The Note will not argue
that transracial adoptions should be favored over same-race adoptions.
Rather, it will argue that transracial adoption is, at the very least,
preferable to the current shortage of black permanent homes for black
children.
This Note will challenge the preference for same-race adoption on two
grounds. Both of these grounds suggest that transracial adoption serves
the best interests of children, but they provide separate and rather
different frameworks for lawyers, legislators, and judges to understand
transracial adoption. First, the Note will argue that transracial
adoption fits within, rather than deviates from, biological matching
goals in adoption proceedings. This ground employs the traditional
adoption paradigm of biological matching to justify transracial
adoption. Second, and more importantly, the Note will demonstrate that
transracial adoption offers unique benefits to adopted children, such
that the very fact of racial difference helps make adoptive families
work. At the very least, these benefits should encourage judges,
adoption professionals, and legislators to reevaluate any skepticism
they may have toward transracial adoption.
The Note will proceed in four parts. Part I will discuss biological
matching, the traditional basis of adoption, and it will offer
justifications for it. Biological matching, at first glance, may appear
mutually exclusive with transracial placements. Part II, however, will
examine whether transracial adoption is actually inconsistent with the
notion of biological matching, arguing that transracial adoption is
itself a form of a biological match. Because there are biological
families containing parents and children with different racial
backgrounds, a biological model for transracial adoptive families does
exist. Part II thus will provide a framework for those involved in
adoption decisions to conceive of transracial adoption as consistent
with the traditional understanding of adoption placements.
Part III will briefly trace arguments particular to racial, rather
than biological, matching in the transracial adoption debate. It will
discuss the debate's focus on racial identity and cultural benefits and
note the scholarship's lack of attention to the unique benefits in
transracial adoption. Part IV will argue that the benefits of
transracial adoption justify such placements, especially when the
alternative for black children is significant delay or nonadoption.
Rather than work within a traditional understanding of adoption, as the
first argument does, this second ground relies on a justification unique
to transracial adoption: that the racial dissimilarity between parent
and child produces particular benefits. Section A will identify two sets
of benefits: direct benefits to the child and indirect benefits by way
of parental expectations. The child may directly benefit from this
obvious difference because its reinforcement of her biological
"otherness" may encourage her to accept both her adoptive and
racial identities. The child may indirectly benefit because the obvious
difference may reduce unrealistic parental expectations. When parents
are reminded about their child's biological "otherness" and
there is no racial similarity between parent and child, the child is
likely to have freedom to develop her own individuality, as well as be
duly recognized for her efforts in accomplishing success, rather than
have others inaccurately credit her accomplishments as inherited from
her parents. Section B will use the notion of "passing" in the
disability context to further explore the benefits of transracial
adoption. Just as an exposed disability makes it unlikely that the
individual can hide his impairment and reject his identity as disabled,
the obvious racial dissimilarity in transracial adoption prevents a
child from passing as her parents' biological offspring and rejecting
her adoptive status.
The Note will conclude that two separate grounds argue in favor of
transracial adoption. First, transracial placements do not necessarily
contradict the biological matching model in adoption placements. Thus,
it is possible for judges and others involved in the adoption decision
to conceive of transracial adoption as fitting within the traditional
understanding of adoption matches. Second, and more importantly,
transracial adoption offers unique benefits that serve the interests of
a child waiting to be adopted. The realistic alternative to transracial
adoption is nonadoption. When weighed against that harm, the unique
benefits of transracial adoption argue in favor of placing black
children with available white couples.
[a1]. J.D., University of Virginia, 200 |