Dorothy E. Roberts,
excerpted from
Welfare and the Problem of Black Citizenship ,
105 Yale Law Journal 1563 -1602, 1576-1584 (April, 1996)
(216 Footnotes Omitted) Book Reviews: Pitied But Not
Entitled: Single Mothers and the History of Welfare. by Linda Gordon. New
York: the Free Press, 1994. Pp. viii, 419. $22.95; The Color of Welfare:
How Racism Undermined the War on Poverty. By Jill Quadagno. New York:
Oxford University Press, 1994. Pp. viii, 240. $24.00
One way of understanding the injustice of the current welfare system is
to examine how its stratified structure distinguishes between citizens and
subjects. Citizens, primarily wealthy and middle-class white Americans,
receive government assistance as a dignified entitlement. Subjects, who
are disproportionately Black, are stigmatized as undeserving recipients of
public charity. I explore in this part several ways in which the form of
government aid known as welfare denies to recipients the rights of
citizenship.
A. The Distinction Between Citizens and Subjects
The stratification of our welfare system that distributes benefits
according to race and gender also differentiates between two classes of
inhabitants -- citizens and subjects. Citizens receive welfare as an
entitlement: Government has an obligation to support citizens as
compensation for their social contribution or as a prerequisite to their
full participation in political and economic life. For example, the
government pays citizens Social Security benefits that are unencumbered by
behavioral conditions, caseworker investigations, or social stigma.
Subjects, on the other hand, receive inferior, inadequate, and
stigmatizing relief at the government's discretion. Poor mothers who
receive AFDC, for example, are considered unworthy of government
assistance; their benefits, set below the poverty level, are conditioned
on conformance to behavioral rules and submission to government
inspection. This surveillance of welfare recipients' everyday lives is so
contrary to the government's respect for citizens that it unmistakably
marks these families as government subjects. Black organizers who agitated
for relief entitlements during the Depression suggested that the
investigation of applicants' morals was a violation of citizenship rights.
One complained:
"Your Administrators here in Baltimore take it upon themselves to
inquire into the morals of the applicant. . . . The writer does not
believe that the letter of the Relief law, or even its spirit gives the
Administrators that authority. May I mention that in France, to hold a
moral inquest upon the applicant for aid is forbidden by law." Given
this connection between citizenship and entitlement to welfare, it is not
surprising that current welfare reform proposals include the elimination
of public assistance for undocumented immigrants.
The critical difference between these two forms of welfare lies in
their relation to individuals' autonomy. While welfare for citizens
enables them to be self-ruling persons, welfare for subjects enables the
government to rule them. Gordon makes this distinction in her defense of
welfare entitlements: "Citizens have rights to which they are
entitled by law, and losing this understanding endangers the republic. . .
. Moreover, the feeling of entitlement is also vital to the republic. It
is the attitude of citizenship, the essence of independence; without it we
would have subjects, not citizens."
The very relegation of subjects to inferior programs that supervise and
humiliate them reinforces their lack of citizenship qualities while
bolstering the virtues of the citizens who receive dignified entitlements.
Citizens' compensation by social insurance makes them appear independent
and self- sufficient; subjects' receipt of charity makes them appear
dependent and irresponsible. Current welfare reform rhetoric condemns
mothers who receive AFDC for transmitting a pathology of "welfare
dependency" to their children. According to this view, reliance on
this form of welfare reflects a lack of work ethic and leads to a myriad
of social problems, including crime, unwed motherhood, and long-term
poverty. Yet Americans do not view reliance on Social Security as
"dependency" at all, despite the program's strong redistributive
effects and the millions of nonworking wives and children who in fact
depend on its benefits for subsistence. Gordon gives the following example
of the downward-spiraling process that results from stigmatizing welfare
recipients:
The stigmas of "welfare" and of single motherhood intersect;
hostility to the poor and hostility to deviant family forms reinforce each
other. The resentment undercuts political support for the program, and
benefits fall farther and farther behind inflation. The resulting
immiseration makes poor single mothers even more needy and less
politically attractive. The economic downturn of the last decade has
deepened both the poverty and the resentment, and created the impression
that we are experiencing a new, unprecedented, and primarily minority
social problem. Thus, Black single mothers' inferior status in the welfare
state has intensified their political and economic marginalization, making
them even less worthy of citizenship rights. By casting their need for
public assistance as "dependency," welfare reform rhetoric
suggests that these women lack the independence required to be citizens,
entitled to dignified government support.
B. Welfare as a Waiver of Privacy
One of the key differences between welfare extended to citizens and
welfare extended to subjects is the degree to which each conditions its
benefits on government intrusion into recipients' privacy. Public relief
for single mothers is structured to permit bureaucratic supervision of
clients in order to determine their eligibility based on both means and
morals testing. Citizens avoid these impositions because they receive
their benefits in the form of entitlements that are not subject to the
discretion of caseworkers, supervisors, or administrators. Since welfare's
inception, states have conditioned payments on mothers' compliance with
standards of sexual and reproductive morality, such as "suitable
home" or "man in the house" rules. More recently, welfare
mothers have been required to undergo mandatory paternity proceedings
involving state scrutiny of their intimate lives. Over the last three
years, at least thirty states have applied for federal waivers allowing
them to change their welfare programs to incorporate a form of behavior
modification.
Means testing and morals testing allow welfare bureaucrats to place
recipients under surveillance to check for cheating or lapses in
eligibility. Such testing also forces recipients to assume a submissive
stance lest offended caseworkers cut them from the rolls. A Black
domestic's experience with poor relief in the 1930s remains typical of
welfare recipients today:
"The investigators, they were like detectives, like I had
committed a crime. . . . I had to tell them about my life, more than if I
was on trial . . . the investigator searched my icebox . . . I was ashamed
of my life . . . that's how you're made to feel when you're down and out
like you're nothing better than a criminal."
Privacy doctrine does not shield from state intrusion people who
receive welfare as subjects; rather, their acceptance of government
benefits constitutes a waiver of privacy. Because families are not
entitled to government support, the Supreme Court has reasoned, the
government may force them to open up for inspection, shrink, rearrange, or
break up in order to qualify for benefits. Courts sometimes find egregious
invasions of poor families' privacy to be unconstitutional, but most of
the day-to-day decisions of family life remain vulnerable to legitimate
state supervision. While poor single mothers (subjects) must endure
government surveillance for their paltry benefits,
"self-sufficient" traditional families (citizens) receive huge
public subsidies -- Social Security, tax breaks, and government-backed
mortgages -- without any loss of privacy.
The Supreme Court invalidated early welfare eligibility requirements,
such as AFDC's "man in the house" rule, designed to
"legislate morality" of recipients. Other precedents, however,
affirm the state's power to condition eligibility for benefits on
conformity with majoritarian family norms. In Dandridge v. Williams, for
example, the Court upheld Maryland's regulation that placed an absolute
cap of $250 monthly per family, regardless of the family's size or
financial need. The Court found that the state's interest in encouraging
employment was a sufficiently rational reason to defeat recipients' equal
protection challenge. The Court rejected the objection that some families
had no employable member on the ground that "the Equal Protection
Clause does not require that a State must choose between attacking every
aspect of a problem or not attacking the problem at all."
Nor do welfare recipients fare well under the unconstitutional
conditions doctrine, which provides that the government may not condition
the conferral of a benefit on the beneficiary's surrender of a
constitutional right, although the government may choose not to provide
the benefit altogether. The Court has avoided the unconstitutional
conditions problem in cases involving public assistance to the poor by
distinguishing between direct state interference with a protected activity
and the state's mere refusal to subsidize a protected activity. The
former, the Court concedes, raises a constitutional issue because it
involves state action, whereas the latter is a constitutionally
insignificant failure to act. For example, the Court refused to require
the state or federal governments to pay the cost of abortion services for
poor women, even though they pay for the expenses incident to childbirth,
reasoning that "[a]lthough government may not place obstacles in the
path of a woman's exercise of her freedom of choice, it need not remove
those not of its own creation." By regarding welfare benefits as an
undeserved subsidy, the Court allows the state to treat recipients as
subjects whose behavior may be modified to fit current social policy.
C. Welfare and Conditions on Reproduction
The goal of some welfare reform proposals is to discourage poor women
from having children. These measures include both "family cap"
legislation, which denies additional benefits for children born to women
already on welfare, and proposals for cash bonuses to encourage these
women to use Norplant. This degree of government control over reproductive
decisionmaking would surely amount to a violation of citizens' procreative
liberty if imposed directly by law. Protection of such deeply personal
matters from government intrusion is "[a]t the heart of
liberty." I have described government restrictions on procreation as
a form of dehumanization:
The right to bear children goes to the heart of what it means to be
human. The value we place on individuals determines whether we see them as
entitled to perpetuate themselves in their children. Denying someone the
right to bear children -- or punishing her for exercising that right --
deprives her of a basic part of her humanity. When this denial is based on
race, it also functions to preserve a racial hierarchy that essentially
disregards Black humanity. In thinking about welfare's relationship to
citizenship, I have come to view provisions designed to deter welfare
recipients from having children as another denial of citizenship rights.
One of the privileges of citizenship is the ability to contribute one's
children to the next generation of citizens. Subjects, on the other hand,
are considered unworthy of adding their offspring to the national
community. This aspect of citizenship explains, as well, the present
campaign to deny automatic citizenship to children born in the United
States of undocumented immigrant parents.
D. Welfare and Forced Labor
Welfare work policies also reflect the distinction between citizens and
subjects. Welfare for citizens addresses defects in the economic structure
in order to protect citizens' economic security. Welfare for subjects, on
the other hand, attempts to change the individual's character in order to
improve her motivation or ability to work. The most popular welfare reform
provisions are those that attempt to end welfare dependency by requiring
recipients to work at government-created jobs or by cutting off benefits
after a set period of years.
Programs that force recipients to perform menial labor for subsistence
benefits resemble involuntary servitude more than the creation of
meaningful work. Work programs cannot possibly enable untrained and poorly
educated women to achieve financial self-sufficiency, especially in an
economy structured against women and with diminishing demand for unskilled
workers. Any work disincentive that exists for welfare mothers is caused
not by overly generous welfare benefits, but by the miserable conditions
of available full-time jobs: poverty wages, loss of welfare benefits, and
inadequate child and health care. In the end, workfare programs leave poor
mothers worse off economically because they remain at the same AFDC level
but incur the added costs of going to work. Treating AFDC recipients as
citizens rather than as subjects would require dramatic economic and
social changes, including aggressive job creation, a higher minimum wage
or a guaranteed minimum income, subsidized child and health care, and
elimination of inequalities in the labor market.
Pitied But Not Entitled and The Color of Welfare reveal how welfare
policy was structured to maintain a Black menial labor force. The fear
that welfare would allow recipients to resist poverty wages was a chief
justification for excluding Blacks from New Deal welfare programs and
opposing guaranteed-income proposals during the 1970s. As one Georgia
Democratic Congressman warned in opposition to President Nixon's
guaranteed- income proposal, " 'There's not going to be anybody left
to roll these wheelbarrows and press these shirts."' In addition,
welfare officials used work programs as a source of Black labor to fill
degrading jobs. The subsequent "deindustrialization" of the U.S.
economy has rendered Black menial labor largely superfluous and cast the
masses of Black Americans even further from citizenship status.
|